Pages

Tuesday, February 4, 2020

How Should we Regulate Child Sex Robots: Restriction or Experimentation?




[This is a cross-post from the BMJ Sexual and Reproductive Health blog. It is a short precis of my paper "Regulating Child Sex Robots: Restriction or Experimentation?"]

In 2017, the Crown Prosecution Services (CPS) decided to clamp down on the importation of child sex dolls into the UK. In doing so, they faced a problem. There was no established legal rule that explicitly banned the purchase and sale of these items. Consequently, the CPS had to get creative. They turned to an old 1876 law – the Customs Consolidation Act – that banned the importation of “obscene” items into the UK. Arguing that child sex dolls were obscene items, the CPS successfully prosecuted several individuals for purchasing them online and having them shipped to the UK.

In doing this, the CPS argued that they were acting in the interests of child protection. They argued that the purchase of child sex dolls was not an isolated phenomenon. Individuals who purchased them were likely to engage with other forms of child pornography, which could, in turn, lead to or encourage offences against children in the real world.

Child sex dolls are inanimate, human-like artifacts used for the purposes of sexual stimulation and gratification. But, given current technological trends, it is quite likely that people will create animate and robotized forms of these dolls in the near future. They are already doing this with adult forms of sex dolls. This raises the obvious question: what should the legal system do about these devices? Should we follow the lead of the CPS and look to ban their development, sale and use? Or should we permit them to be created on the grounds that, unlike other forms of child pornography, the creation of a child sex robot or doll does not involve any direct harm to real children?

In my article, ‘Regulating Child Sex Robots: Restriction or Experimentation?’, I survey the possible answers to this question and make a specific case for pessimism about our capacity to adequately answer them. This pessimism is itself, I suggest, a reason to favour restricting these devices. One of the first things I point out is that how you feel about this issue is likely to depend on your default assumptions about the legitimate role of the law in human life. If you adopt a strongly libertarian attitude, you might be inclined to permit the development, sale and use of these devices. After all, if there is no direct or obvious harm to another, then there is no justification for state intervention. On the other hand, if you adopt a more paternalistic attitude, or embrace precautionary attitude to the regulation of new technologies, then you might be inclined to favour state intervention and restriction, even in the absence of direct harm. Perhaps on the grounds that encouraging such devices could lead to harm to others.

I initially make the case for an alternative view. I argue that there is a prima facie case to be made in favour of restricting practices that are both extremely offensive to the majority of people and morally corrosive to particular individuals. In other words, I make the prima facie case for a mild form of legal moralism in relation to child sex robots. Legal moralism is a controversial and well-debated idea. Many people of a liberal persuasion will tend to oppose it. But what I point out in the article is that some moralistic bans are difficult to reject, even for those who are staunchly liberal in their outlooks and attitudes (as I believe I am). So, for example, laws that prohibit the desecration of dead corpses strike many people as justifiable, even when such desecration causes no direct or indirect harm to others. It seems that there is something symbolically harmful about the act that warrants legal restriction.

The category of deeply offensive symbolic harms is difficult to define. This is a problem because we wouldn’t (or, at least, I wouldn’t) want to encourage excessive state scrutiny of that category. But although the category may be difficult to define, child sex robots would seem to be the paradigmatic example of something that fits within it. It is plausible to suppose that we can justifiably restrict them on this ground without sliding down a slippery slope to more paternalistic regulation of practices that harm no one other than the people who engage in them.

This argument for restrictive regulation of child sex robots is, however, just a prima facie argument and quite a weak one at that. Someone could easily come along and argue that although these devices are symbolically harmful and deeply offensive, they are, nevertheless, socially beneficial. Perhaps child sex robots serve a greater good? Perhaps they could be used to treat child sex offenders in the same way that methadone is used to treat heroin addicts. In July 2014, at a conference in Berkeley, the roboticist Ronald Arkin suggested that this is a hypothesis that might be worth investigating. Arkin’s hypothesis, if confirmed, would provide support for the idea that some specific uses of this technology should not be banned; in fact, they should be incentivized or encouraged by the legal system. But, in many ways, the truth or falsity of the Arkin hypothesis is a red herring. The immediate challenge for the regulatory system is whether regulations should be put it place to facilitate its testing.

This is where my pessimism comes into play. I am not convinced that we should encourage the testing of the Arkin hypothesis because I don’t believe that we will come to a satisfactory conclusion about it. There are three reasons for this pessimism. First, past experience with analogous empirical debates (e.g. the link between use of violent pornography and real-world sexual offending) do not bode well for this investigation. Those debates are marred by both politicized and polarized research findings, often without clear policy implications. Second, ongoing scandals about the institutional biases and weaknesses of scientific research suggest that we may not be well-equipped to find out the truth about something like Arkin’s hypothesis. Third, and finally, therapeutic interventions for child sex offending are already exceptionally difficult to adequately test. There is no reason to think it will be any easier if the therapeutic intervention involves child sex robots.

I conclude by suggesting that this pessimism about our capacity to test the Arkin hypothesis is perhaps itself a reason to favour restrictive regulation of child sex robots. If we are going to open this Pandora’s Box, we should do so with utmost caution.



4 comments:

  1. This comment has been removed by the author.

    ReplyDelete
  2. I don't think one has to ground the rationale for the prevention of 'desecrating' dead bodies on any moralistic grounds. For one, it introduces a 'clumsy' or generally unpersuasive concept back into use. And too many of those willing to justify prejudices can use it without any real argument. I think alternative routes exist: a dead body can be seen as a property belonging to the family, protected under property rights, subject to criminal damage and theft laws. Or perhaps property held under a will of the recently deceased person, just as his other remaining assets are held under a will, and protected by the state. This can work in conjunction with viewing his body as something sacrosanct and worthy of protection more than just 'mere property', just like highly valued possessions are i.e a historical artefact. And it can be deemed automatically part of his will (his body being protected by law like a property right) just like had he died without an official will, intestate.

    I agree with the rest of your points, just don't think re-introducing afresh a 'dying' line of reasoning is worthwhile by going with the moralism route.

    ReplyDelete
  3. In regards to your dead corpse desecration analogy, I would like to write a brief response:

    I don't necessarily think that desecrating a dead corpse should be illegal if it is genuinely done with the consent of the deceased party (consent that would obviously be given before death if it is to be given at all). After all, if one believes in bodily autonomy, then one could argue that people have a right to do with their bodies whatever they please--and that includes things such as having their bodies be desecrated after their deaths, assuming that they are actually able to find someone who is willing to desecrate their bodies after their deaths. The challenge might be in ensuring that genuine consent was indeed given to this desecration before one's death, but if genuine consent can indeed be established in regards to this, then I don't necessarily think that it's the state's business to intervene in regards to this.

    Now, one could come up with another, more offensive analogy: Let's say that there is some video game that allows you to reenact the Holocaust. This video game itself would be harmless but would simulate an evil deed. So, would it be justified to ban it? A freedom absolutist could say No, it would be unjustified to ban it. However, someone else could take a different route and say that this video game is so offensive that is indeed deserves to be banned. You would think that this would be analogous to child sex dolls, right? Well, not quite. Because with this Holocaust video game, banning it wouldn't actually result in a significant negative effect on anyone. Sure, people might have one less game to play, but this isn't actually going to be crucial for them. In contrast, banning child sex dolls is going to deprive people with pedophilic inclinations of any legal and anywhere near remotely moral outlet to express their sex drives. So, this could compel people with pedophilic inclinations (well, those who are moral and who thus aren't going to molest actual children) to give up *any* semblance of a decent, satisfactory sex life, to get castrated, to engage in self-harm, to commit suicide, to fall into a deep and enduring depression, to drink alcohol in excess, to use drugs, and/or et cetera. After all, I would presume that this is how some gay people have historically acted when they didn't have any available and legal outlet for their sex drives--and pedophilia, like homosexuality, is an unchangeable and incurable sexual orientation. So, there is much more actual harm from banning things such as child sex dolls than there is from banning an offensive Holocaust video game or whatever. To make these two scenarios comparable, one would need to imagine a certain group of people who derive sexual satisfaction from playing this Holocaust video game and who cannot achieve long-term sexual satisfaction in any other way. In these changed circumstances, banning this offensive Holocaust video game would indeed be much more objectionable because now banning it would result in a sizable amount of actual harm--whereas this wasn't actually true before. So, when it comes to banning something, a part of the question that needs to be asked is this--just how much additional harm is banning this thing going to result in relative to not banning this thing? And yet, depriving someone of a decent, satisfactory sex life for their entire lives would certainly be considered quite significant harm. Anyway, if there is significant harm in banning this thing relative to not banning this thing, then it would be considerably less justifiable to ban this offensive thing than it would be if banning this thing didn't actually result in significant harm to anyone. Does that make sense?

    ReplyDelete
  4. By the way, John, do you also consider things such as rape fantasy porn to be offensive? Do you believe that it should be outlawed? What about if it is (hypothetically) the only way that certain people can achieve sexual satisfaction?

    ReplyDelete